Is Tennessee's Ruling Against Gay Marriage a Setback for the Cause?

Alexander Demyanenko/Shutterstock.com

 

Connecting state and local government leaders

The decision to uphold a same-sex marriage recognition ban snapped a streak of court victories.

The great streak of court victories for gay marriage was broken on Tuesday: A state court in Kingston, Tennessee, became the first to uphold a state ban on gay marriage since the Supreme Court’s decision last year in United States v. Windsor

The decision in Borman v. Piles-Borman, written by Circuit Judge Russell Simmons, holds that Tennessee does not have to recognize the marriage of two male Tennessee residents who had traveled to Iowa to wed. They sought state recognition because they had decided to divorce—and Iowa won’t permit their divorce unless one is an Iowa resident.

Tennessee’s “anti-recognition law,” which this decision upholds, limits the state's recognition of out-of-state marriages to those between a man and a woman. The decision is, as the judge notes, of limited effect—“the decision of this Court will only be binding on this case and this Court.” In fact, a federal district court in Nashville has already struck down the anti-recognition law, and an appeal is pending before the Sixth Circuit. (District court decisions don't bind other courts, so Simmons was not bound by the federal court's decision, particularly since his court sits in a different district of the Sixth Circuit than the one where the ruling was issued.)  

More than two dozen courts in the 14 months since Windsor have struck down laws against gay marriage. Simmons's decision, then, seems to be an outlier; his opinion appears unlikely to start a lower-court stampede in the other direction. But it is worth considering as window into the arguments of gay-marriage opponents.

Seen through that lens, the important thing about Simmons’s opinion is its even tone. He notes that in 1972, the Supreme Court briefly considered a same-sex couple’s challenge to a state marriage law, and dismissed it “for want of a substantial federal question.” Other courts have held that the 1972 case, Baker v. Nelson, is no longer binding because the law has changed—particularly in light of Windsor. In that case, the majority held that the federal government has to recognize valid state same-sex marriages; thus, most subsequent judges have reasoned, the federal question can hardly be seen as “insubstantial.” Simmons, however, argues that Windsor didn’t overrule Baker; indeed, Windsor didn’t even mention Baker. 

Simmons goes on to hold that the state’s ban on same-sex marriage is valid. His reasons aren’t very original: Only men and women can procreate. “Biology alone, therefore, provides a rational explanation for Tennessee’s decision not to extend marriage to same-sex couples,” he writes. The right to marry, he agrees, is “fundamental.” Like other opponents of same-sex marriage, however, he insists that same-sex marriage is not “marriage” at all, but something brand-new and strange. “The battle is not whether or not marriage is a fundamental right but what unions are included in the definition of marriage,” Simmons writes. 

That truly is the central question. If same-sex marriage is “marriage,” then the “biology” argument takes us nowhere, since marriage is permitted to couples who can’t have children. But if it isn’t “marriage,” it is something scary and new (“newer than cell phones or the Internet,” Justice Samuel Alito said during oral arguments in the Proposition 8 cases).

Distrust of newness is the essence of old-style conservatism. “A spirit of innovation is generally the result of a selfish temper and confined views,” Edmund Burke wrote in his Reflections on the Revolution in France. “People will not look forward to posterity, who never look backward to their ancestors.” The satisfaction of present needs may create future problems, and so should be avoided if possible.

American law fundamentally rejects that view of the world. Confronted with a claim of individual right, our constitutional tradition insists that government justify itself now, with actual evidence and not vague fears. But the Burkean temper is not hateful; it is simply timorous. Simmons's decision doesn't rant and rave, even if its basis is fundamentally irrational. Advocates of same-sex marriage (I’ve been one for 25 years) need to take note of that fact.

But is all opposition to gay marriage inspired by hate? And if it isn't, does that make a legal difference?

Gay marriage is on a roll, and victory can bring hubris. A number of voices have begun to insist that any opposition to same-sex marriage is “bigotry.” Thus, for example, a popular dating site demands that its patrons stop using a specific web browser because an official of the browser company once opposed same-sex marriage. Thanks, but if I were dating, I’d find a less paternalistic dating site. That level of outrage is justified only if opposition to gay marriage is moral leprosy, like white supremacy or Holocaust denial. But is all opposition to gay marriage inspired by hate? And if it isn’t, does that make a legal difference?  

Adam Liptak shrewdly explored this question in a recent column in The New York Times. The key to Justice Anthony Kennedy’s thought, and vote, he notes, is the concept of “animus.” Anti-gay measures like §3 of DOMA, Kennedy has written, are adopted for the sole purpose of making gays less than equal, and thus are unconstitutional.  

Kennedy’s antagonists on the Court, however, react to the “animus” claim like World Cup footballers rolling on the ground in simulated agony. They insist that the only meaning of “animus” is “bigotry.” Justice Antonin Scalia, in his Windsordissent, claimed that Kennedy was portraying the opponents as “unhinged members of a wild-eyed lynch mob.”

There’s a misconception here—that without hatred, there can be no legal “animus.” Consider Scalia’s own explanation, in his dissent in Lawrence v. Texas, of why a state can outlaw gay sex. “Many Americans do not want persons who openly engage in homosexual conduct as partners in their business, as scoutmasters for their children, as teachers in their children’s schools, or as boarders in their home,” he wrote. “They view this as protecting themselves and their families from a lifestyle that they believe to be immoral and destructive.” 

In other words, the majority did not hate gay people, they simply wanted to keep them apart from others. 

That wish to exclude a group from full equality must be backed by something more than dislike, or disapproval, or suspicion, or unfamiliarity. Otherwise, no matter how calmly it may be expressed, it is “animus.” People who feel that wish, however, may not feel hatred at all; calling them “bigots” doesn’t advance the dialogue. Instead, patient argumentation should address their arguments, not assault their character. Argument breaks down fear; assault intensifies it. And assault recasts the moral valence of the movement: Instead of crusaders for equality, marriage advocates begin to seem (as Alito has suggested) intolerant and “bigoted” themselves.  

Gay marriage has been on a roll. That roll is likely to continue, Simmons's decision notwithstanding. But hubris is a mortal danger to any movement, and gay-marriage activists must avoid premature triumphalism. Assaulting opponents as “bigots” is poor strategy. Many of them, like Simmons, are simply confused and a bit afraid. Asking the Supreme Court, and in particular Kennedy, to brand them all as evil may backfire. 

(Image via Alexander Demyanenko/Shutterstock.com)

NEXT STORY: Subscription Confirmed

X
This website uses cookies to enhance user experience and to analyze performance and traffic on our website. We also share information about your use of our site with our social media, advertising and analytics partners. Learn More / Do Not Sell My Personal Information
Accept Cookies
X
Cookie Preferences Cookie List

Do Not Sell My Personal Information

When you visit our website, we store cookies on your browser to collect information. The information collected might relate to you, your preferences or your device, and is mostly used to make the site work as you expect it to and to provide a more personalized web experience. However, you can choose not to allow certain types of cookies, which may impact your experience of the site and the services we are able to offer. Click on the different category headings to find out more and change our default settings according to your preference. You cannot opt-out of our First Party Strictly Necessary Cookies as they are deployed in order to ensure the proper functioning of our website (such as prompting the cookie banner and remembering your settings, to log into your account, to redirect you when you log out, etc.). For more information about the First and Third Party Cookies used please follow this link.

Allow All Cookies

Manage Consent Preferences

Strictly Necessary Cookies - Always Active

We do not allow you to opt-out of our certain cookies, as they are necessary to ensure the proper functioning of our website (such as prompting our cookie banner and remembering your privacy choices) and/or to monitor site performance. These cookies are not used in a way that constitutes a “sale” of your data under the CCPA. You can set your browser to block or alert you about these cookies, but some parts of the site will not work as intended if you do so. You can usually find these settings in the Options or Preferences menu of your browser. Visit www.allaboutcookies.org to learn more.

Sale of Personal Data, Targeting & Social Media Cookies

Under the California Consumer Privacy Act, you have the right to opt-out of the sale of your personal information to third parties. These cookies collect information for analytics and to personalize your experience with targeted ads. You may exercise your right to opt out of the sale of personal information by using this toggle switch. If you opt out we will not be able to offer you personalised ads and will not hand over your personal information to any third parties. Additionally, you may contact our legal department for further clarification about your rights as a California consumer by using this Exercise My Rights link

If you have enabled privacy controls on your browser (such as a plugin), we have to take that as a valid request to opt-out. Therefore we would not be able to track your activity through the web. This may affect our ability to personalize ads according to your preferences.

Targeting cookies may be set through our site by our advertising partners. They may be used by those companies to build a profile of your interests and show you relevant adverts on other sites. They do not store directly personal information, but are based on uniquely identifying your browser and internet device. If you do not allow these cookies, you will experience less targeted advertising.

Social media cookies are set by a range of social media services that we have added to the site to enable you to share our content with your friends and networks. They are capable of tracking your browser across other sites and building up a profile of your interests. This may impact the content and messages you see on other websites you visit. If you do not allow these cookies you may not be able to use or see these sharing tools.

If you want to opt out of all of our lead reports and lists, please submit a privacy request at our Do Not Sell page.

Save Settings
Cookie Preferences Cookie List

Cookie List

A cookie is a small piece of data (text file) that a website – when visited by a user – asks your browser to store on your device in order to remember information about you, such as your language preference or login information. Those cookies are set by us and called first-party cookies. We also use third-party cookies – which are cookies from a domain different than the domain of the website you are visiting – for our advertising and marketing efforts. More specifically, we use cookies and other tracking technologies for the following purposes:

Strictly Necessary Cookies

We do not allow you to opt-out of our certain cookies, as they are necessary to ensure the proper functioning of our website (such as prompting our cookie banner and remembering your privacy choices) and/or to monitor site performance. These cookies are not used in a way that constitutes a “sale” of your data under the CCPA. You can set your browser to block or alert you about these cookies, but some parts of the site will not work as intended if you do so. You can usually find these settings in the Options or Preferences menu of your browser. Visit www.allaboutcookies.org to learn more.

Functional Cookies

We do not allow you to opt-out of our certain cookies, as they are necessary to ensure the proper functioning of our website (such as prompting our cookie banner and remembering your privacy choices) and/or to monitor site performance. These cookies are not used in a way that constitutes a “sale” of your data under the CCPA. You can set your browser to block or alert you about these cookies, but some parts of the site will not work as intended if you do so. You can usually find these settings in the Options or Preferences menu of your browser. Visit www.allaboutcookies.org to learn more.

Performance Cookies

We do not allow you to opt-out of our certain cookies, as they are necessary to ensure the proper functioning of our website (such as prompting our cookie banner and remembering your privacy choices) and/or to monitor site performance. These cookies are not used in a way that constitutes a “sale” of your data under the CCPA. You can set your browser to block or alert you about these cookies, but some parts of the site will not work as intended if you do so. You can usually find these settings in the Options or Preferences menu of your browser. Visit www.allaboutcookies.org to learn more.

Sale of Personal Data

We also use cookies to personalize your experience on our websites, including by determining the most relevant content and advertisements to show you, and to monitor site traffic and performance, so that we may improve our websites and your experience. You may opt out of our use of such cookies (and the associated “sale” of your Personal Information) by using this toggle switch. You will still see some advertising, regardless of your selection. Because we do not track you across different devices, browsers and GEMG properties, your selection will take effect only on this browser, this device and this website.

Social Media Cookies

We also use cookies to personalize your experience on our websites, including by determining the most relevant content and advertisements to show you, and to monitor site traffic and performance, so that we may improve our websites and your experience. You may opt out of our use of such cookies (and the associated “sale” of your Personal Information) by using this toggle switch. You will still see some advertising, regardless of your selection. Because we do not track you across different devices, browsers and GEMG properties, your selection will take effect only on this browser, this device and this website.

Targeting Cookies

We also use cookies to personalize your experience on our websites, including by determining the most relevant content and advertisements to show you, and to monitor site traffic and performance, so that we may improve our websites and your experience. You may opt out of our use of such cookies (and the associated “sale” of your Personal Information) by using this toggle switch. You will still see some advertising, regardless of your selection. Because we do not track you across different devices, browsers and GEMG properties, your selection will take effect only on this browser, this device and this website.